Blog of the International Journal of Constitutional Law

Reviewing Ireland’s Abortion Regime

Eoin Carolan, University College Dublin

The recent death of a woman from septicaemia following a miscarriage has focused attention on the legal regime regulating the carrying out of abortions within Ireland. Since the Constitution was amended in 1983 to insert a provision recognising the right to life of the unborn, the issue of abortion has been a consistent, if sporadic, source of public controversy in Ireland. Coming, as it did, at a time when the government was already considering its response to a recent European Court of Human Rights ruling that Ireland’s abortion regime is in breach of the Convention, the death increased the pressure on Ireland’s political class to engage with an issue which successive governments have sought to avoid. That culminated with this week’s announcement by the Government of the manner – if not the detailed content – of how it intends to proceed to regulate the availability of abortion in Ireland.

While the case has attracted much publicity and comment, a full investigation of the circumstances surrounding the death has yet to be carried out. As such, a number of matters remain unclear. This includes the important question of whether the death would have been avoided if a termination had – as the couple reportedly requested – been carried out at an earlier stage of the miscarriage. With the facts undetermined, it would plainly be inappropriate to speculate about the constitutional rights or wrongs of this tragic case.

The point of this piece is instead to provide some brief background to Ireland’s constitutional position and to identify some of the aspects of the current regime that have given rise to particular difficulties: an exercise which may have wider significance, given the recent trend in various American states to follow the Irish approach of conferring constitutional protection on the unborn.

In 1983, a majority of voters approved a proposal to amend the Constitution by inserting the following text as a new Article 40. 3. 3:

“The State acknowledges the right to life of the unborn and, with due regard to the equal right to life of the mother, guarantees in its laws to respect, and, as far as practicable, by its laws to defend and vindicate that right”.

The proposal for an amendment was prompted by concerns that the Griswold-like recognition of a right to martial privacy by the Irish courts in McGee v. A.G. would ultimately lead to a Roe v. Wade-type ruling from the Supreme Court.

Although the question of abortion remained – and remains – capable of provoking strong feelings on both sides of the argument, the issue was one with which the main Irish political parties proved generally reluctant to engage. The perception seems to have been that the political costs of taking action on such a controversial and divisive question were sufficiently high that it should be avoided if possible. Furthermore, the political pressure of the issue was somewhat dissipated by the proximity to Ireland of a more liberal abortion regime in the United Kingdom. Thus, the Irish authorities presided over a system which effectively regarded the prohibition of abortion as a moral and constitutional imperative but which was simultaneously aware that substantial numbers of Irish women travelled to the United Kingdom each year for the purpose of carrying out an abortion: perhaps a classic example of the Irish solution to an Irish problem.

The relative political complacency over this situation was disrupted, however, by the litigation in A.G. v. X in 1992. This concerned an attempt by the Attorney General, in purported performance of the State’s obligation under Article 40. 3. 3, to obtain an injunction preventing a teenage rape victim from travelling to the United Kingdom for an abortion. The case attracted substantial public comment and ultimately led to a ruling by a majority of the Supreme Court that “if it is established as a matter of probability that there is a real and substantial risk to the life, as distinct from the health, of the mother, which can only be avoided by the termination of her pregnancy, such termination is permissible, having regard to the true interpretation of Article 40,s.3, sub-s. 3 of the Constitution”. In circumstances where psychological evidence indicated that there was a risk of suicide if the pregnancy continued, the majority held that termination was constitutionally permissible.

The decision in X was followed by further referenda in 1992 and in 2002 which cumulatively confirmed the existence of a right to travel, a right to information concerning overseas abortion services, and that the test of a “real and substantial risk to the life of the mother” could be satisfied on either physical or psychological grounds. This remains the position under the Constitution at present.

Despite the relative clarity of the constitutional position on abortion since 1992, Ireland’s abortion regime has continued to cause difficulties in practice.

First of all, there has been a noticeable reluctance on the part of successive governments to introduce legislation giving effect to the Supreme Court’s decision in X. This has led to a problematic situation in which patients and doctors must look to an 1861 statute criminalising abortion and a lengthy Supreme Court decision,  as construed by professional medical bodies, for guidance as to the availability or otherwise of an abortion in particular cases. It was this uncertainty which the European Court of Human Rights relied on in finding Ireland in breach of Article 8 of the Convention in A, B & C. v. Ireland,  concluding that “the uncertainty generated by the lack of legislative implementation of Article 40.3.3, and more particularly by the lack of effective and accessible procedures to establish a right to an abortion under that provision, has resulted in a striking discordance between the theoretical right to a lawful abortion in Ireland on grounds of a relevant risk to a woman’s life and the reality of its practical implementation”.

Secondly, the text of Article 40. 3. 3 has generated significant uncertainty about the permissibility or otherwise of various unanticipated medical or scientific developments. While the Supreme Court has clarified that the “unborn” does not include the pre-implantation embryo, substantial ambiguity remains over the legality of a range of activities including stem cell research, fertility treatment and surrogacy. Once again, governments have proved reluctant to legislate on any of these issues. Indeed, the fact that there is a clear constitutional dimension to these questions seems to have provided both a political incentive and a pretext to allow these questions to be determined on an ad hoc basis by the courts.

Finally, while the decision in X provided some clarity on the constitutionality of abortion, the circumstances of the case highlight an inherent difficulty with the text of Article 40. 3. 3 which continues to exist: namely, the problems posed by its insistence on an a priori and acontextual equivalence between the rights of mother and unborn. While the notion of rights-holders as equal has obvious force in political rhetoric and (perhaps) moral philosophy, it poses clear problems for a court in cases where the rights come into conflict. Constitutional law is, in many cases, all about assessing the relative value of rights in a particular context. Determining that balance in advance in a way which ignores the possibility of conflict means that the text of Article 40. 3. 3 has, in many respects, little value when that conflict occurs. The struggles of both the majority and minority in X to identify factors which would justify their decision underline the difficulties – from the perspective of both practical reasoning and democratic legitimacy – which face a court in effectively choosing between rights which the Constitution states to be equal.

Regardless of one’s personal views on abortion policy, Ireland serves as a warning of the risks associated with the hasty constitutionalisation of complex or difficult issues.  Poor draftsmanship has certainly exacerbated the problems with the Irish position. Hard cases, it would appear, are an inevitable consequence of bad law.

However, it seems reasonable to suggest that some of these difficulties would have arisen even under a better drafted amendment. By their generalist nature, constitutions are ill-suited to resolving complex issues. It seems unrealistic to expect a constitution to contain the sort of detailed substantive and procedural rules necessary to operate even a limited form of abortion regime. Yet, addressing a specific policy issue by means of a generalist provision is likely to give rise in other contexts to interpretative ambiguities and unanticipated consequences.

Furthermore, the Irish experience suggests that the ‘resolution’ of a controversial issue at the constitutional level may discourage political action by providing sufficient legal authority, however imprecise, to make legislative inaction a viable, if inefficient, option. Where the costs of political decision-making are high, the incentive for politicians of having those costs borne by another institution may be too tempting to avoid. The reality is that a constitutional amendment which was argued to be necessary to prevent the judiciary from adjudicating on abortion has instead led to a situation in which difficult issues of policy have been almost entirely left to an unhappy Supreme Court to determine. As Ireland’s hard cases and ambiguous uncertainties show, this is a highly unsatisfactory way to regulate complex questions.

Comments

13 responses to “Reviewing Ireland’s Abortion Regime”

  1. Killian Donoghue Avatar
    Killian Donoghue

    Eoin,
    Excellent post. I have a few questions, though, which you may be able to answer. By acknowledging the right to life of the unborn, does the Constitution guarantee the unborn the right to fair procedure? If so, what are the consequences of that?

    Whether or not you believe that the unborn is a human being with human rights, the Irish Constitution acknowledges the right to life of the unborn. And constitutional jurisprudence requires that where a fundamental right––such as the right to life––is threatened fair procedure applies.

    If the unborn is entitled to fair procedure, and in the absence of legislation or a Supreme Court decision defining ‘unborn’, does this require that a court or legal tribunal should decide when an abortion is permissible in order to vindicate the unborn’s right to life and fair procedure? (is the unborn entitled to legal representation?) Or does it require a legal definition of unborn: does the right to life of the unborn acknowledged by the Constitution begin at conception, or when life is viable outside of the womb?

    There are a lot of ifs , buts and whethers there. Hopefully you can shed some light on this issue for me.

  2. Richard Albert Avatar

    Eoin, this is so fascinating. Your post has prompted many thoughts and questions on my end.

    I wonder if I might ask you just one comparative question about the implications of participatory theory for achieving constitutional peace on the politically divisive question of abortion.

    Let me describe what I understand to be the current state of affairs on abortion in three western liberal democracies.

    In the United States, the right to procure an abortion was declared to exist by the national Supreme Court in 1973. Scholars at the time argued that the Court short-circuited the popular and legislative deliberative processes that had been ongoing and developing within the states on whether abortion should be criminalized. Since then, political actors and the people have remained divided on the normative constitutionality of abortion.

    In Canada, the national Supreme Court invalidated a federal statute criminalizing abortion in 1988. But the Court did not foreclose the possibility that Parliament could criminalize abortion. Parliament subsequently tried twice to pass another law criminalizing abortion, but both bills were defeated. Since then, no serious political actor has taken an anti-abortion position as a campaign matter, recognizing that the nation has achieved a relatively stable consensus on the legality of abortion.

    And in Ireland, as I understand it, the baseline rules on abortion were ultimately decided by referenda. I also understand that there are strong political and social consensuses on abortion in Ireland.

    Assuming these three case studies are correctly described, do you think one can interpret them illustrating that the likelihood of achieving constitutional peace on abortion is directly related to the degree of popular participation in resolving such a deeply divisive matter of moral contention?

    I also wonder whether the heterogeneity of the American and Canadian populations, versus the relative homogeneity of the Irish population, can also help explain at least part of this.

    Thanks for your post.

  3. Eoin Carolan Avatar
    Eoin Carolan

    Thanks to both Killian and Richard for the insightful comments and queries.

    On Richard’s more general comparative observations, I agree that there are important differences in the way the debates about abortion have been framed in the jurisdictions you mention; and that those differences are probably explained in part by the different sites in which the political contestation has taken place.

    For example, it strikes me as an outside observor that the American debate is in part coloured by a perceived illegitimacy in having the matter ‘determined’ by the court, whereas that seems to find less of an echo in Ireland where the issue was initially constitutionalised by a vote of the People.

    However, Im not sure its strictly correct to say there is strong consensus on abortion in Ireland. It has historically been a very divisive issue, as shown by the number of referenda that have been held to try to address the issue since 1983.

    This is also complicated by the fact that experience here shows the divergence that can exist between popular attitudes in the abstract and, on the other hand, popular reaction to specific situations – the ‘hard cases’ that have arisen under Ireland’s current constitutional position.

    A good recent illustration of this was the result of an opinion poll which came up with the contradictory finding that 85% indicated they wanted the government to legislate for the X case (which means allowing abortion where the mother’s life is threatened, including by suicide) while 63% reported wanting a constitutional amendment to limit the X case, by excluding a threat of suicide as a grounds for abortion, but still allowing abortion, where the mother’s life is threatened outside of suicide.

    So I dont think Ireland necessarily validates the idea that popular participation may promote constitutional peace in terms of an agreed resolution – but it may contribute to constitutional peace in the sense that it maintains some sense of popular legitimacy in relation to the fact of the contestaton itself.

    On Killian’s question, what would be required in terms of legal certainty would depend on the context. The X case provides one example of a legal process which was initiated to determine the relative rights of the unborn there. Similarly, the unborn was represented by legal counsel in the Article 26 reference on the Abortion Informaton Bill. So there are some potential processes there in particular contexts. When the detail of any new legislation or regulations become clear, they might address some of the issues you raise.

  4. Richard Albert Avatar

    Eoin, thanks for your helpful reply on this. Interrogating this constitutional comparison in terms of the relative popular procedural legitimacy of the constitutional settlement is a better approach than making the comparison in terms of the more indeterminate idea of constitutional peace.

  5. […] ongoing campaign to amend the Irish constitutional approach to abortion (about which there has been renewed controversy and focus in recent […]

  6. Ascenttzj Avatar
    Ascenttzj

    which is carried out by the printing

  7. Foamoqz Avatar
    Foamoqz

    or their samples written

  8. Artisangyr Avatar
    Artisangyr

    XVII century was Nicholas Jarry [fr].

  9. Glasswss Avatar
    Glasswss

    Many calligraphers have acquired

  10. Furrionddy Avatar
    Furrionddy

    or their samples written

  11. Bluetoothhqk Avatar
    Bluetoothhqk

    the spread of parchment.

  12. Professionalxsv Avatar
    Professionalxsv

    Since the era of Charlemagne

  13. Juicerwfq Avatar
    Juicerwfq

    for Countess Louise of Savoy

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *